Or: “Can an International Treaty Make
Barack Obama President For Life?”
First, a programming note. As often is the case, much of my writing
energy has been consumed as of late in court documents that have not yet been
released on the internet (indeed in many case, have not yet been filed.) But I am on break and in that break, I can
talk about other things. I will also
catch up on the big legal occurrences last week shortly.
Today the
Supreme Court handed down its opinion in Bond
v. U.S., and while the decision was unanimous, it was a surprisingly
contentious unanimity. But first a
little background.
There is an
infamous line in the otherwise unnotable opinion on obscenity from Justice Potter
Stewart. First Amendment doctrine has
long held that “obscenity” (more or less, hard core porn) is an exception to
freedom of speech or the press that can therefore be banned, even with criminal
consequences. Of course anyone with
basic Google skills can quickly discover that such bans are like the proverbial
finger in the dam as it bursts, but whether such bans are of any practical use
or not is beside the point. They exist
and therefore the Supreme Court had to wrestle with how to define that term: obscenity.
So Jacobellis
v. Ohio (1964) is mostly
unremarkable. It involved a movie called
The Lovers, which I have never viewed
but you can read a review here,
but to be blunt nothing said in the opinion was too unusual. It was from the time when the Supreme Court
felt that the way to manage the issue of obscenity was to personally review
every single allegedly obscene movie, book, exposing these justices to whatever
deleterious social effects these movies supposedly have. Still, it was a pretty straightforward
application of the prevailing legal standard at the time: whether to the
average person, applying contemporary community standards, the dominant theme
of the material taken as a whole appeals to prurient interest, so long as it
was utterly without redeeming social importance. In other words movies you watch just to see
people having various kinds of sex, with no attempt to have a plot, characters,
social significance, etc. Which still
doesn’t really tell you where the line between the good stuff is and the stuff
that can be banned, does it?
Again, all of
this is actually not remarkable for the doctrine at the time and the case is
pretty much forgotten except for what Justice Stewart wrote in his concurrence:
[U]nder
the First and Fourteenth Amendments criminal laws in this area are
constitutionally limited to hard-core pornography. I shall not today attempt
further to define the kinds of material I understand to be embraced within that
shorthand description; and perhaps I could never succeed in intelligibly doing
so. But I know it when I see it, and
the motion picture involved in this case is not that.
(Emphasis
added.) In legal circles that quote ("I know it when I see it") has
not been treated very kindly and deservedly so.
The Supreme Court has regularly stated that limitations on free
expression needed to be clearly defined, so as to avoid the “chilling effect”
that occurs where people try to steer far clear of the line between free speech
and criminal sanction. Yes, you and I
just talking can say, “we all know what kinds of movies we are talking
about.” But in law that kind of
vagueness is ordinarily fatal... except
when the Supreme Court is the one purveying the vagueness.
So that brings
us to Bond v. United States, a case
handed down just today, which can be read here. This case wouldn’t seem at first glance to
relate in any way to obscenity, but it does have a downright Stewart-like
quality in one respect.
Roberts wrote
the majority opinion, joined without expressed reservation by all but Alito,
Thomas and Scalia, who each wrote separate concurrences. The basic story is that a woman (Bond) found
out her husband was cheating on her and therefore made a feeble attempt to harm
the other woman with chemicals. The
“other woman” only ended up suffering a minor chemical burn on her thumb. I don’t want to diminish what amounts to an
assault, but here’s what it isn’t: it isn’t a rocket filled with chemicals shot
on a village. It was this:
Bond
stole a quantity of 10-chloro-10H-phenoxarsine (an arsenic-based compound) from
her employer, a chemical manufacturer. She also ordered a vial of potassium
dichromate (a chemical commonly used in printing photographs or cleaning
laboratory equipment) on Amazon.com. Both chemicals are toxic to humans and, in
high enough doses, potentially lethal. It is undisputed, however, that Bond did
not intend to kill Haynes. She instead hoped that Haynes would touch the
chemicals and develop an uncomfortable rash.
Between
November 2006 and June 2007, Bond went to Haynes’s home on at least 24
occasions and spread the chemicals on her car door, mailbox, and door knob.
These attempted assaults were almost entirely unsuccessful. The chemicals that
Bond used are easy to see, and Haynes was able to avoid them all but once. On
that occasion, Haynes suffered a minor chemical burn on her thumb, which she
treated by rinsing with water.
So Haynes
called the local police and they didn’t care, but the federal government chose
to charge Bond with using a chemical weapon in addition to theft of the mails.
You see a few
years back we ratified a treaty on the use of chemical weapons, and passed
legislation consistent with that act. So
this presented a few questions for the court:
1) Did the Chemical
Weapons Convention Implementation Act apply to this conduct?
2) Did
Congress ordinarily have the power to enforce such a law in this situation?
3) If Congress
didn’t ordinarily have the power to enforce this law, would the fact that this
is implementing a treaty make the law Constitutional?
Well, we did
not get to those last two questions directly.
Instead the Court decided, much as it had with the Obamacare case, to
read the statute as to duck the issue entirely.
There is a common constitutional doctrine that if a statute is
ambiguous, and you have two possible readings of it, that the courts will avoid
the interpretations that leads to a serious doubt to its constitutionality.
For the
government—and Justice Scalia—the argument is simple. First in 18 U.S.C. § 229, it states that “it
shall be unlawful for any person knowingly... to develop, produce, otherwise
acquire, transfer directly or indirectly, receive, stockpile, retain, own, possess,
or use, or threaten to use, any chemical weapon[.]” Then in 18 U.S.C. § 229f it says that “chemical
weapons”
means
the following, together or separately:
(A)
A toxic chemical and its precursors, except where intended for a purpose not
prohibited under this chapter as long as the type and quantity is consistent
with such a purpose.
(B)
A munition or device, specifically designed to cause death or other harm
through toxic properties of those toxic chemicals specified in subparagraph
(A), which would be released as a result of the employment of such munition or
device.
(C)
Any equipment specifically designed for use directly in connection with the
employment of munitions or devices specified in subparagraph (B).
Then in turn the statute defines a “purpose not
prohibited under this chapter” as follows:
(A)
Peaceful purposes. - Any peaceful purpose related to an industrial,
agricultural, research, medical, or pharmaceutical activity or other activity.
(B)
Protective purposes. - Any purpose directly related to protection against toxic
chemicals and to protection against chemical weapons.
(C)
Unrelated military purposes. - Any military purpose of the United States that
is not connected with the use of a chemical weapon or that is not dependent on
the use of the toxic or poisonous properties of the chemical weapon to cause
death or other harm.
(D)
Law enforcement purposes. - Any law enforcement purpose, including any domestic
riot control purpose and including imposition of capital punishment.
So just to be
clear, the LAPD can have a chemical filled Scud missile, so long as it is for
the purpose of law enforcement.
Humor aside,
then the application of the law is pretty straightforward. As noted above the substance is toxic, so it
would seem to be “a toxic chemical or its precursors” fitting that part of the
definition of chemical weapons. And she did
use it. So the only outstanding question
would seem to be whether this was a “peaceful purpose” and the lower court
brushed that aside without even considering it: assault is not a peaceful
purpose. And Roberts concedes this
syllogism makes a degree of sense.
But, Roberts
said,
The
problem with this interpretation is that it would “dramatically intrude[ ] upon
traditional state criminal jurisdiction,” and we avoid reading statutes to have
such reach in the absence of a clear indication that they do.
Look, Roberts said in paraphrase, when we read the law there are tons of
hidden assumptions behind them.
For
example, we presume that a criminal statute derived from the common law carries
with it the requirement of a culpable mental state—even if no such limitation
appears in the text—unless it is clear that the Legislature intended to impose
strict liability.
That is true
as far as it goes, but the court is all over the place in articulating that
hidden assumption. Is the issue
federalism? Then simply reading a
requirement of a connection to interstate commerce into the statute would be sufficient
as the courts had done in the past. Or
one could take this line from Roberts’ opinion “The Federal Government
undoubtedly has a substantial interest in enforcing criminal laws against
assassination, terrorism, and acts with the potential to cause mass suffering”
and use it to imply it has to be connected to such a traditional area of
federal concern. Any one of these
articulated approaches would have had some decent support, but the problem is
that Roberts doesn’t effectively argue in favor of any of them and you get the
feeling that he is just rejecting this conviction based more on feel than a
specific legal doctrine, writing things such as: “When used in the manner here,
the chemicals in this case are not of the sort that an ordinary person would associate
with instruments of chemical warfare” and “the global need to prevent chemical
warfare does not require the Federal Government to reach into the kitchen
cupboard.” Absurd or unconstitutional
results are a useful guide to reading a statute, but sometimes Congress does
intend that and if you are going to say that hidden assumptions are preventing
you from reading words that ordinarily read this way from being read this way,
you have to be clearer about what those assumptions are. Saying this stuff is “not of the sort that an
ordinary person would associate with instruments of chemical warfare” is not as
memorably terse as “I know it when I see it” but how exactly does it differ
from Stewart’s infamous definition of obscenity?
By contrast,
Scalia, who has a strong and relatively consistent belief in following the
plain text of the laws, says we should read the statute as applying to this
crime and therefore invalidate the
statute. One thing that really
struck me, reading Scalia’s opinion is how acidic it is (sorry for the
unintentional pun). Scalia can be
witheringly sarcastic and this is a prime example of it. To pick up a few examples:
It
is the responsibility of “the legislature, not the Court, . . . to define a
crime, and ordain its punishment.” United States v. Wiltberger, 5 Wheat. 76, 95
(1820) (Marshall, C. J., for the Court). And it is “emphatically the province
and duty of the judicial department to say what the law [including the
Constitution] is.” Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803) (same). Today,
the Court shirks its job and performs Congress’s.
Or:
The
Court’s account of the clear-statement rule reads like a really good lawyer’s
brief for the wrong side, relying on cases that are so close to being on point that someone eager to reach the favored
outcome might swallow them.
Or:
Imagine
what future courts can do with that judge-empowering principle: Whatever has
improbably broad, deeply serious, and apparently unnecessary consequences . . .
is ambiguous!
Or:
The
same skillful use of oh-so-close-to-relevant cases characterizes the Court’s
pro forma attempt to find ambiguity in the text itself,
Or:
The
Court retorts that “it is not unusual to consider the ordinary meaning of a
defined term, particularly when there is dissonance between that ordinary
meaning and the reach of the definition.” Ante, at 16. So close to true!
Which is
probably as close as any Supreme Court opinion is ever likely come to actually
saying the other side is full of it. And
this next example is fairly dripping with sarcasm:
But
there is nothing either (1) realistic or (2) well known about the presumption the
Court shoves down the throat of a resisting statute today. Who in the world
would have thought that a definition is inoperative if it contradicts ordinary
meaning? When this statute was enacted, there was not yet a “Bond presumption”
to that effect—though presumably Congress will have to take account of the Bond
presumption in the future, perhaps by adding at the end of all its definitions that
depart from ordinary connotation “and we really mean it.”
And Scalia
even throws back into Roberts’ face the “I know it when I see it” line,
describing how the new law effectively reads:
Henceforward,
a person “shall be fined . . . , imprisoned for any term of years, or both,”
§229A(a)(1)—or, if he kills someone, “shall be punished by death or imprisoned
for life,” §229A(a)(2)—whenever he “develop[s], produce[s], otherwise
acquire[s],transfer[s] directly or indirectly, receive[s], stockpile[s],
retain[s], own[s], possess[es], or use[s], or threaten[s] to use,” §229(a)(1),
any chemical “of the sort that an
ordinary person would associate with instruments of chemical warfare,” ante,
at 15 (emphasis added).
Really,
seriously, you have to read both opinions to take in just how sarcastic and
derisive Scalia was towards Roberts. I
suspect Roberts is the kind of person who can laugh this kind of criticism off,
but for many people this would be the end of any kind of cordial relationship.
Mind you, both
men agree on the ultimate conclusion.
This conviction was wrongfully gained.
This is not to say what Bond did was legal, just that it is illegal
under state, not federal, law. The
difference is that Roberts interpreted the law as to avoid any conflict with the
Constitution, and Scalia wanted to say that the law applied to this conduct and
therefore it was unconstitutional.
As we are
talking about hidden assumptions, I think it is fair to suspect there are
hidden undercurrents here, too. This
statute was passed in 1998. I wonder how
many really truly vile people have been convicted of doing exactly what this
law prohibits? If the statute is struck
down they would all have to be freed, unless they are charged with other
crimes. Was Roberts worried about setting
lose a bunch of terrorists and their ilk?
This blog has become somewhat of a testament to the damage letting one
sociopath loose can do, so I can easily sympathize with his position.
Meanwhile, for
Scalia I think some of this is lingering anger over Roberts’ decision to uphold
Obamacare. As you might recall, that
involved interpreting a penalty as a tax, in order to avoid rendering it
unconstitutional. Kennedy, Thomas, Alito
and Scalia wanted to interpret the law as written and strike it down, just as
Scalia did here and I think he is a bit fed up with that tendency.
And in general
Scalia just believes in following the text and the idea that an ordinary citizen should
be able to open up the statute books and have some chance of figuring out what
is expected of him. As Scalia wrote
today
A
criminal statute must clearly define the conduct it proscribes. If it does not
“‘give a person of ordinary intelligence fair notice’” of its scope, United States v. Batchelder, 442 U. S.
114, 123 (1979), it denies due process.
It’s an old
fight. Do you just interpret the law
exactly as written and let Congress fix its own messes? Or do you save them from their own dumb
selves sometimes, especially considering that it could have consequences on a
lot of innocent people? Roberts is
evidently willing to go a considerable distance in the direction of saving
Congress from itself, and Scalia isn’t.
The other
issue lurking here was the issue of the treaty making power. As Roberts notes in the opinion, there was no
attempt by the government to justify this law as a matter of the commerce
power. Instead they rested their entire
argument on the theory that because it was implementing a treaty it was
inherently constitutional.
The
Government replies that this Court has never held that a statute implementing a
valid treaty exceeds Congress’s enumerated powers. To do so here, the
Government says, would contravene another deliberate choice of the Framers: to
avoid placing subject matter limitations on the National Government’s power to
make treaties. And it might also undermine confidence in the United States as
an international treaty partner.
This is a
theory that has been pushed in academic circles for a while. I was exposed to it in law school and I
thought it was a poor theory then. It
all goes back to the supremacy clause of the constitution. Here’s what it says:
This
Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in
Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the
Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the
Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or
Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding.
So let’s parse
this a bit. The Constitution is the law
of the land. So is any act of Congress
“which shall be made in Pursuance thereof.”
The courts have read that last phrase to mean that only laws that follow
the Constitution are covered by this language, which seems to be a pretty
natural reading.
But there is a
small cadre of academics who say, “ah!
There is no such limiting language when it comes to treaties! Therefore even treaties that are ordinarily
unconstitutional are the supreme law of the land! So if we make a treaty with Latvia that says
that their respective rulers shall hold their offices for life, then we have to
accept that Obama is President for life!”
Some liberals
love this theory because 1) it represents the idea that we might have to
subjugate our parochial laws to “enlightened” international ideals (because
naturally we would only be treating with countries which are more enlightened,
instead of, say, China or Saudi Arabia), 2) it also means we might have to
subsume ourselves to something like the U.N., and 3) because they happen to
control the Senate and the White House where treaties are made. I suspect that if the Presidency and Senate
should fall into Republican hands, liberal academics will fall back in love
with the idea that the Treaty-making power is limited.
And mind you
there is some precedent for this. For
instance, my in-laws had a family friend who was looking to become a citizen
and I helped him. I will have to be
vague about this person because my wife and I are being stalked, but I can tell
you he was born in 1939, in the Philippines (thus arguably “Filipino” despite
not being of that heritage), at which point the Philippines was held by the
U.S. So my first question was “why the
hell wasn’t this person already a citizen?”
After all the Fourteenth Amendment states that “[a]ll persons born or
naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are
citizens of the United States.” In what
sense was the Philippines not in the United States at that time? Seemed to me that they were as much part of
America as Hawaii or Alaska—or Porto Rico, for that matter.
But, he
explained to me, in the treaty
ceding the Philippines and Porto Rico from Spain, it stated that “[t]he
civil rights and political status of the native inhabitants of the territories
hereby ceded to the United States shall be determined by the Congress.” This was interpreted by Congress and the
courts as allowing Congress to decide whether persons born there were
citizens of the United States and so the Filipinos were not allowed to be
citizens. This is despite the fact that I
have read of Filipinos being charged with Treason in that period and that in U.S.
v. Wong Kim Ark (1898) the Supreme
Court noted that in colonial times “all persons born under British dominion are
natural-born subjects.” In other words,
the Supreme Court said we were being less generous with our colonists than the
British in that respect.
And there is
equally some language in Missouri
v. Holland (1920) that suggests
such an interpretation in relationship to migrant birds that cross into Canada.
So there is
some precedent, involving screwing millions of brown people out of citizenship
in the United States and protecting certain species of birds, and the left
wants to continue that tradition in general and both Scalia and Thomas wanted
to put an end to that line of thinking.
Scalia’s
primary argument on this point is summed up in this passage:
Under
Article I, §8, cl. 18, Congress has the power “[t]o make all Laws which shall
be necessary and proper for carrying into Execution the foregoing Powers and
all other Powers vested by this Constitution in the Government of the United
States, or in any Department or Officer thereof.” One such “other Powe[r]”
appears in Article II, §2, cl. 2: “[The President] shall have Power, by and
withthe Advice and Consent of the Senate, to make Treaties, provided two thirds
of the Senators present concur.” Read together, the two Clauses empower
Congress to pass laws “necessary and proper for carrying into Execution . . .
[the] Power . . . to make Treaties.”
It
is obvious what the Clauses, read together, do not say. They do not authorize
Congress to enact laws for carrying into execution “Treaties,” even treaties
that do not execute themselves, such as the Chemical Weapons Convention.
So the
argument Scalia hangs his hat on is that even if treaties can go beyond the
Constitution, laws carrying them into effect cannot. Carrying into effect the power to make
treaties, Scalia argues, is stuff like
hiring
treaty negotiators, empower[ing] the Department of State to appoint those
negotiators, form[ing] a commission to study the benefits and risks of entering
into the agreement, or [paying] for a bevy of spies to monitor the
treaty-related deliberations of other potential signatories.
But it doesn’t
extend to implementing the treaty once they are in effect. But honestly, I think that argument is a
little too cute. If a treaty requires us
to set up a military base in country X, Congress is going to have to pass a law
implementing that treaty and yet does any person think that such implementation
is not allowed under the constitution?
Meanwhile Thomas argues that a hidden assumption in the Treaty making
power is that it is limited to foreign relations—that the conduct of a citizen
that has no effect on international relations is not the proper subject of a
treaty. And I don’t see anything
obviously wrong with that, except to note that given the way we have extended
the concept of interstate commerce to ridiculous lengths, I am not sure that
limiting the treaty power to inter-country issues is very much protection.
And it is
worth noting that Scalia and Thomas both resort to arguments from
absurdity. Scalia writes, for instance,
that
If
that is true, then the possibilities of what the Federal Government may
accomplish, with the right treaty in hand, are endless and hardly farfetched.
It could begin, as some scholars have suggested, with abrogation of this
Court’s constitutional rulings. For example, the holding that a statute
prohibiting the carrying of firearms near schools went beyond Congress’s enumerated
powers, United States v. Lopez, 514 U. S. 549, 551 (1995), could be reversed by
negotiating a treaty with Latvia providing that neither sovereign would permit
the carrying of guns near schools. Similarly, Congress could reenact the
invalidated part of the Violence Against Women Act of 1994that provided a civil
remedy for victims of gender motivated violence, just so long as there were a
treaty on point—and some authors think there already is, see MacKinnon, The
Supreme Court, 1999 Term, Comment,114 Harv. L. Rev. 135, 167 (2000).
Thomas does
this less, but he does do it to a degree, writing:
Yet
to interpret the Treaty Power as extending to every conceivable domestic
subject matter—even matters without any nexus to foreign relations—would
destroy the basic constitutional distinction between domestic and foreign
powers. See United States v.
Curtiss-Wright Export Corp., 299 U. S. 304, 319 (1936) (“[T]he federal
power over external affairs [is] in origin and essential character different
from that over internal affairs . . .”). It would also lodge in the Federal
Government the potential for “a ‘police power’ over all aspects of American
life.” Lopez, supra, at 584 (THOMAS, J., concurring). A treaty-based power of
that magnitude—no less than a plenary power of legislation—would threaten
“‘“the liberties that derive from the diffusion of sovereign power.”’” Bond v. United States, 564 U. S. ___,
___ (2011) (slip op., at 9). And a treaty-based police power would pose an even
greater threat when exercised through a self-executing treaty because it would
circumvent the role of the House of Representatives in the legislative process.
See The Federalist No. 52, p. 355 (J. Cooke ed. 1961) (J. Madison) (noting that
the House has a more “immediate dependence on, & anintimate sympathy with
the people”).
And even I do,
for that matter, invoking the specter that, through the treaty making power we
might see Obama become President for life.
Scalia and Thomas don’t think it is inappropriate to ever reason from
avoiding unconstitutional and/or absurd interpretations. They are just disagreeing with how far
Roberts went in doing so.
And bluntly,
it is going a long way for what is actually very simply solved. Yes, the Supremacy Clause doesn’t say that
treaties are the supreme law of the land, pursuant
to the Constitution but there is a very specific reason for that. Before we had our Constitution, we had the
Articles of Confederation and we did have treaties ratified by them. The obvious intent of the founders was to
say, upon ratifying the Constitution that 1) the Articles of Confederation were
no longer the law, 2) all laws passed by Congress under the Articles were no
longer law, but 3) all treaties remained in effect. And this was because we didn’t want to be
seen repudiating those treaties.
But that
limiting language—stating that all treaties ratified “under the Authority of
the United States” is the supreme law of the land—is sufficient. Where does the President get his authority? Where does the Senate get it? From the Constitution. And the Constitution does not grant the
President or the Senate the power to violate it. How can it?
But a sharp
eyed reader might ask: “would this mean that an otherwise unconstitutional
treaty ratified prior to the ratification of the Constitution would still be
the law of the land so long as it was done in line with the Articles of
Confederation?” And the answer is yes,
obviously, and one can be reasonably sure that the founders were not overly
worried about that because 1) they knew what treaties they were dealing with,
and you cannot add a new one today under the Article of Confederation now that
it is defunct.
The title of
this piece made fun of Roberts, in a way, by saying he knows what a chemical
weapon is when he sees it. But in a real
sense, by offering two insufficient theories of limiting the treaty-making
power, and offering a parade of horribles in argument against this far-reaching
interpretation of the treat-making or treaty executing power, Scalia and Thomas
(and Alito who joined them), are almost saying themselves “I know a violation
of the Constitution when I see it.”
Argument from absurdity has validity, especially as a way of waking
yourself up if you are going down the wrong path, but it can’t be the whole
argument. “That can’t be right!” is a
starting point, but that is not a legal standard.
---------------------------------------
My wife and I have lost our jobs due to the harassment of convicted
terrorist Brett Kimberlin, including an attempt to get us killed and to frame
me for a crime carrying a sentence of up to ten years. I know that claim sounds fantastic, but if you
read starting here,
you will see absolute proof of these claims using documentary and video
evidence. If you would like to help in
the fight to hold Mr. Kimberlin accountable, please hit the donation link on
the right. And thank you.
Follow me at Twitter @aaronworthing,
mostly for snark and site updates. And
you can purchase my book (or borrow it for free if you have Amazon Prime), Archangel:
A Novel of Alternate, Recent History here.
And you can read a little more about my
novel, here.
---------------------------------------
Disclaimer:
I have accused
some people, particularly Brett Kimberlin, of reprehensible conduct. In some cases, the conduct is even
criminal. In all cases, the only justice
I want is through the appropriate legal process—such as the criminal justice
system. I do not want to see vigilante violence
against any person or any threat of such violence. This kind of conduct is not only morally
wrong, but it is counter-productive.
In the
particular case of Brett Kimberlin, I do not want you to even contact him. Do not call him. Do not write him a letter. Do not write him an email. Do not text-message him. Do not engage in any kind of directed
communication. I say this in part
because under Maryland law, that can quickly become harassment and I don’t want
that to happen to him.
And for that matter,
don’t go on his property. Don’t sneak
around and try to photograph him.
Frankly try not to even be within his field of vision. Your behavior could quickly cross the line
into harassment in that way too (not to mention trespass and other concerns).
And do not
contact his organizations, either. And
most of all, leave his family alone.
The only
exception to all that is that if you are reporting on this, there is of course
nothing wrong with contacting him for things like his official response to any
stories you might report. And even then
if he tells you to stop contacting him, obey that request. That this is a key element in making out a
harassment claim under Maryland law—that a person asks you to stop and you
refuse.
And let me say
something else. In my heart of hearts, I
don’t believe that any person supporting me has done any of the above. But if any of you have, stop it, and if you
haven’t don’t start.
No comments:
Post a Comment